next up previous
Next: Models for Galactic sources Up: Bayesian model comparison applied Previous: Why not to use


The Bayesian way out: how to use of experimental data to update the credibility of hypotheses

We think that the solution to the above problems consists in changing radically our attitude, instead of seeking for new `prescriptions' which might cure a trouble but generate others. The so called Bayesian approach, based on the natural idea of probability as `degree of belief' and on the rules of logic, seems to us to be the proper way to deal with our problem. A key role in this approach is played by Bayes' theorem, which, apart from normalization constant, can be stated as

$\displaystyle P(H_i\,\vert\,$Data$\displaystyle , I_0) \propto P($Data$\displaystyle \,\vert\,H_i,I_0) \cdot P(H_i\,\vert\,I_0)\,,$ (4)

where $ H_i$ stand the hypotheses that could produce the Data with likelihood $ P($Data$ \,\vert$ $ H_i,I_0)$. $ P(H_i\,\vert\,$Data$ , I_0)$ and $ P(H_i\,\vert\,I_0)$ are, respectively, the posterior and prior probabilities, i.e. with or without taking into account the information provided by the Data. $ I_0$ stands for the general status of information, which is usually considered implicit and will then be omitted in the following formulae.

The presence of priors, considered a weak point by opposer's of the Bayesian theory, is one of the points of force of the theory. First, because priors are necessary to make the `probability inversion' of Eq. (4). Second, because in this approach all relevant conditions must be clearly stated, instead of being hidden in the method or left to the arbitrariness of the practitioner. Third, because prior knowledge can be properly incorporated in the analysis to integrate missing or deteriorated experimental information (and whatever it is done should be stated explicitly!). Finally, because the clear separation of prior and likelihood in Eq. (4) allows to publish the results in a way independent from $ P(H_i\,\vert\,I_0)$, if the priors might differ largely within the members of the scientific community. In particular, the Bayes factor, defined as

$\displaystyle BF_{ij} = \frac{ P(\mbox{\it Data}\,\vert\,H_i) }{ P(\mbox{\it Data}\,\vert\,H_j) }\,,$ (5)

is the factor which changes the `bet odds' (i.e. probability ratios) in the light of the new data. In fact, dividing member to member Eq. (4) written for hypotheses $ H_i$ and $ H_j$, we get

posterior odds$\displaystyle _{ij} = BF_{ij} \cdot$   prior odds$\displaystyle _{ij} \,.$ (6)

Since we shall speak later about models $ {\cal M}_i$, the odd ratio updating is given by

$\displaystyle \frac{P({\cal M}_i\, \vert\, \mbox{\it Data})} {P({\cal M}_j\, \v...
...box{\it Bayes factor}}\, \cdot \frac{P_\circ({\cal M}_i)} {P_\circ({\cal M}_j)}$ (7)

Some general remarks are in order. An analogue of Eq. (4) applies to the parameters of a model. For example, if, given a model $ {\cal M}$, we are interested to the rate of g.w. on Earth, $ r$, Bayes' theorem gives

$\displaystyle f(r \, \vert\, {\it Data}, {\cal M}) \approx f({\it Data}\, \vert \,r, {\cal M}) \times f_\circ(r,{\cal M})\,,$ (8)

where $ f()$ stand for probability density functions (pdf) Also in this case, a prior independent way of reporting the result is possible. The difficulty of dealing with an infinite number of Bayes factors (precisely $ \infty^2$, given each $ r_i$ and $ r_j$) can be overcome defining a function $ {\cal R}$ of $ r$ which gives the Bayes factor with respect to a reference $ r_\circ$. This function is particularly useful if $ r_\circ$ is chosen to be the asymptotic value at which the experiment looses completely sensitivity. For g.w. search this asymptotic value is simply $ r\rightarrow 0$. In other cases it could be an infinite particle mass [3] or an infinite mass scale [4]. In the case of g.w. rate $ r$, extensively discussed in Ref. [5], we get

$\displaystyle {\cal R}_{{\cal M}}(r) = \frac{f({\it Data}\, \vert \,r, {\cal M}...
...vert \,r=0, {\cal M})} = \frac{{\cal L}_{\cal M}(r)}{{\cal L}_{\cal M}(r=0)}\,,$ (9)

where $ {\cal L}_{\cal M}(r)$ is the model dependent likelihood. [Note that, indeed, in the limit of $ r\rightarrow 0$ the likelihood depends only on the background expectation and not on the specific model. Therefore $ {\cal L}_{\cal M}(r=0) \rightarrow {\cal L}_{\cal M_\circ}$, where $ {\cal M_\circ}$ stands for the model ``background alone''.] This $ {\cal R}$ function has the meaning of relative belief updating factor [5], since it tells us how we must modify our beliefs of the different values of $ r$, given the observed data. In the region where $ {\cal R}$ vanishes, the corresponding values of $ r$ are excluded. On the other hand, in the region where $ {\cal R}$ is about unity, the data are unable to change our beliefs, i.e. we have lost sensitivity. The region of transition between 0 and 1 defines the sensitivity bound, a concept that does not have a probabilistic meaning and, since it does not refers to terms such as `confidence', does not cause the typical misinterpretations of the frequentistic `confidence upper/lower limits' (for a recent example of results using these ideas see Ref. [8]). Values of $ r$ preferred by the data are spotted by large value of $ {\cal R}$. We shall in the sequel how a plot of the $ {\cal R}$ function gives an immediate representation of what the data tell about a parameter (Figs. 3 and 4). Another interesting feature of this function is that, if several independent data sets are available, each providing some information about model $ {\cal M}$, the global information is obtained multiplying the various $ {\cal R}$ functions:

$\displaystyle {\cal R}_{{\cal M}}(r\,;\,$All data$\displaystyle ) = \prod_i {\cal R}_{{\cal M}}(r\,;\,$Data$\displaystyle _i)\,.$ (10)



Subsections
next up previous
Next: Models for Galactic sources Up: Bayesian model comparison applied Previous: Why not to use
Giulio D'Agostini 2005-01-09